Ebook: The Sovereign and the Prophets - Spinoza on Grotian and Hobbesian Biblical Argumentation
Author: Fukuoka Atsuko
- Genre: Other Social Sciences // Politics
- Tags: Spinoza, Grotius, Hobbes, Philosophy, Anthropology Philosophical, Person What it is, Axiology, Ethics, Human dignity, Europe, Belgium, France, Germany, Great Britain, Greenland, Italy, Netherlands, Romania, Scandinavia, History, World, Civilization & Culture, Jewish, Religious, Slavery & Emancipation, Women in History, History, Europe, History, Humanities
- Series: Brill’s Studies in Intellectual History 268
- Year: 2018
- Publisher: BRILL
- Language: English
- pdf
Tracing Old Testament topics recurrent in Grotian and Hobbesian discourses on the church-state relationship, Atsuko Fukuoka recontextualizes Spinoza’s Theologico-political Treatise and clarifies its historical import for Dutch debates on religion, state power, and liberty.
---------------------
installed on the marble floor of the Burgerzaal in the new city hall of his
native Amsterdam. This planisphere symbolized the contemporary progress
of the philosophia nova, astronomy and celestial cartography in particular.
Amsterdam was the proud host of leading publishers in these disciplines and
it was their representative, Willem Janszoon Blaeu, who first produced in print
what is considered to be the original version of the planisphere engraved into
city hall (cover; the caption of the planisphere reads, ‘Coeli planisphaerium describebat
Guiljelmus Blaeu anno 1628’). Spinoza, as a young man, must have been one of those who were
fascinated by the new view of the world.
The planisphere speaks to an important aspect of Spinoza’s intellectual life:
positioned at the heart of city hall, it was a symbolic representation of the fact
that scholarship never exists in a vacuum, but is situated in, and correspondingly
dependent on, the society and political system within which the intellectual
works. Blaeu’s publishing house itself gives an example of this. The
company, succeeded by his son Joan, once suffered a raid by the Amsterdam
magistracy, who had complied with the requests of Calvinist ministers to
supress the Blaeus’ commitment to non-orthodox publications, especially
Socinian works, for which Amsterdam was again the well-known host. Later,
as an adult, striving to himself be a contributor to the philosophia nova, Spinoza
took up the task of thinking fundamentally about the tension between scholarship
and society. His involvement resulted in the publication of the Tractatus
theologico-politicus (TTP) in 1670.
The present book centrally concerns how this treatise redefined the relationship
between state and church ( jus circa sacra), and how it articulated a
theory for intellectual liberty on that basis (libertas philosophandi). The TTP
stemmed from a milieu in which the question of whether or not the government
could be the protector of students of truth was crucial. This question
embraced another problematic question: How can rulers know truth? It was
assumed that God is the one who knows truth, and therefore He should be
asked in order that His will be discerned. But given that there are people
professionally trained to understand His will, should rulers simply ask them,
instead of directly asking God? Most of the time, it may be safe to do so. And
yet, in some critical cases, do rulers not need to ask God themselves and judge
what is true for themselves, at their own risk and responsibility? To formulate
the same idea according to the contemporary frame of thought: Who occupies
the position directly below God to transmit His will to the people? In short,
who is the true mediator of His will on earth?
These are the questions that the present book traces. They entailed the
points of debate that were already heated in the early years of the Republic’s
history, particularly among the friends and foes of Hugo Grotius in the 1610s.
Almost two generations later, the same set of questions must have vexed the
Amsterdam city magistrates (schepenen), who in early summer 1668 were to
judge a friend of Spinoza, Adriaen Koerbagh (1633–1669), accused of infringing
on the anti-Socinian legislation of 1653 issued by the States of Holland,
by authoring a highly audacious criticism of religion and church.4 The magistrates
might have felt encouraged to assert their own judgment against
clerical opposition by a Ferdinand Bol painting decorating their chamber
(schepenkamer) in the city hall, ‘Moses’s Descent from Mount Sinai with the
Ten Commandments’. As Michael Rosenthal pertinently contextualized, Bol’s
painting had been designed to endorse such leadership by civil authorities.
It represents Moses solemnly bringing the tablet of the Decalogue from God
to the people, while Aaron, the high priest, kneels to his brother as if humbly
remembering his past misjudgment that had wrongly led the Hebrews into the
worship of the golden calf.5 Despite the artwork’s message, however, the magistrates
examining Koerbagh substantially acquiesced to the judgment of the
Calvinist ministers who were demanding that Koerbagh’s deed necessitate a
severe punishment. Spinoza’s TTP appeared shortly after this traumatic event,
which ended with Koerbagh’s death in prison in October 1669.
Bol’s painting is a visual reminder of the larger conversation in which
Spinoza participated. The role of the biblical text as a medium for discussing the
relationship between state, church and liberty is central to Spinoza’s TTP.
The focus of the present book is, in the narrowest sense, to analyse Spinoza’s
choice and interpretation of quotations from the Old Testament and how this
relates to his contemporaries’ comparable biblical readings that were current
in the Dutch political context that prompted him to compose the TTP. I thus
share Rosenthal’s interest in the TTP’s immediate historical context and the
Bible’s function as example within this context.7 And yet my interest does not
consist simply in examples as such, but rather in how the examples comprise
a complex network of competing interpretations within the context of debate.
Crucial, therefore, is an analytical comparison that accounts not only for differing
interpretations of the biblical text, but also for the different translations.
The axis of the comparison is the paradigmatic question that appears even in
Bol’s painting in the Chamber of Magistrates: Who mediates the reign of God?
The objects of comparison start with treatises produced in the abovementioned
milieu of Grotius during the Remonstrant controversy over the
church-state relationship, and most importantly include Thomas Hobbes’s
Leviathan, Part III in particular. It is well known that this work attracted significant
interest in the Dutch Republic. Joan Blaeu, then a member of the ruling
body of Amsterdam, arranged a new Latin translation of Leviathan by Hobbes
himself to be included in Opera philosophica.8 The eventual publication of this
Latin translation came in 1668, one year after the publication of a Dutch translation
which Abraham van Berckel (1639–1686), another friend of Spinoza, had
prepared, and a relative of Koerbagh had printed.9 Recent scholarship suggests
that Hobbes’s biblical interpretation in Part III of Leviathan could be regarded
as a possible ‘prototype’ of the TTP’s engagement with the Bible.10 While it
is true that historical clues presently available cannot absolutely determine
whether Spinoza did read Leviathan while writing the TTP, this does not diminish
the necessity for a detailed comparison between the biblical interpretations
of these two treatises. The historical relevancy of such comparison is vouched
for, especially because Hobbes shares with Spinoza and other Dutch theoreticians
a strong interest in the question concerning divine will’s mediators, and
it is in Leviathan that this question receives Hobbes’s full-length investigation
based on biblical exegesis.
Indeed, a close observation of Spinoza’s and Hobbes’s biblical interpretations
reveals that the overlap between their topics and quotations converges,
among other issues, on matters related to the question of mediating agents, the
direct interlocutors with God, and how they relay God’s revelation and His laws
to humankind. Therefore, this book discusses the four subjects that are most
pertinent to this question of mediation: (1) jus circa sacra, or the sovereign’s
right over religion: Spinoza associates this issue with the role of the ruler to
mediate God’s ‘reign’ or ‘kingdom’ (regnum) to humankind;12 (2) the authority
of the Bible; (3) media of revelation, or the question of how God spoke to the
prophets; and (4) the Spirit of God.
With an investigation into the two philosophers’ consonances and dissonances
at its center (chapters 4–8), the present book also investigates several
major Dutch theoretical works that discuss the church-state relationship.
These works were related to the reception of Hobbes in the Dutch Republic
and to the issues pertinent to the TTP, and therefore help us to understand the
link between Hobbes and Spinoza. The first group of sources comprises those
produced during the controversy between the Remonstrants and the Contra-
Remonstrants in the first two decades of the seventeenth century (chapter 1).
In this period, ‘[t]he main patterns of argument had been laid down’13 for the
later debates on the church-state relationship, so that Hobbes’s ideas, which
started to exercise influence on Dutch soil from the middle of the century,
quickly merged with the ideas that had been raised by Grotius and his friends.
And yet the ideas of the Dutch Remonstrants and those of Hobbes contain
significant differences, too. After summarizing the pivotal ideas of Part III of
Leviathan in chapter 2, the next chapter compares Hobbes’s ideas with those
of the Remonstrant polemicists on the one hand, and with representative
authors belonging to the new philosophical generation that arose in the 1650s
and 1660s, on the other (chapter 3). Interpretation of a topical biblical passage,
Deut. 17:8–13, provides the point of comparison for the analyses in this
chapter. While the theoreticians discussed in these chapters are chronologically
prior to the TTP, chapter 9 concerns one from the period that succeeded
it: Ulrik Huber, the Frisian father of universal public law ( jus publicum universale).
His theory of jus circa sacra testifies not only to the impact Hobbes and
his students had on the landscape of the subject, but also to the centrality that
the question of divine will’s mediation occupied in defining the relationship
between the sovereign, the church, and the individual.
Jus circa sacra, as the right of the secular authority over religious matters
was called at the time, is a many-sided concept. The establishment of this
phrase has been attributed by Johannes Heckel to Grotius’s work during the
Remonstrant controversy, De imperio summarum potestatum circa sacra (completed
in 1617 and first published in 1647), though not in combination with jus,
but rather with imperium.14 The designation derived from a similar expression,
potestas ecclesiastica circa sacra, which was current among Reformed theologians
in the Holy Roman Empire. Differentiated from potestas ecclesiastica ‘in’
sacra, power reserved for clerics alone, potestas ecclesiastica ‘circa’ sacra—the
share of lay magistracy—originally carried a connotation that the power of
secular rulers was limited to non-essential, if not peripheral, matters of religion.
The concept existed under the long shadow of King Uzziah, who dared
to administer religious rituals himself, rejecting the help of priests, and who
was punished immediately by God (2 Chr. 26:16–23). Though the word circa
continued to be used as a part of the fixed phrase, the precise implication of
this word—that the secular jurisdiction is limited to non-essential matters of
religion—was at issue. As a search for logical arguments that could defend
the supremacy of the lay magistracy over clerics, the Remonstrants’ debate in
favour of the imperium circa sacra was at the same time a process of conceptually
refining the meaning of summa potestas (‘sovereign power / sovereignty’)
for the young republic.
Still, in the second half of the century, the lack of a clear definition between
the two poles of authority was deeply felt among the States Party sympathizers
and this accounted for the popularity of Hobbes’s political works among
them. Although the Englishman Hobbes employed only the phrase ‘ecclesiastical
power’ (potestas ecclesiastica)15 and not imperium / jus circa sacra (or
its equivalent in English), the continuity of the problem was clear enough to
his Dutch readers. Spinoza’s TTP (1670) signals that he knew the term jus circa
sacra as a current catchphrase indicating issues concerning church and state,
as the title of chapter 19, ‘it is shown that jus circa sacra belongs wholly to the
sovereign powers’,16 testifies. The fact that Ulrik Huber used the word combination
jus circa sacra in the title of a section concerning that subject in his
textbook on jus publicum (De jure civitatis libri tres: 1672, 1684, and 1694) further
illustrates that the term was well established.17 Characteristic of these last two
authors is their engagement with jus circa sacra as an issue no longer concerning
sovereignty theory alone, but also tightly connected with the defence of
what each thought to be freedom—libertas philosophandi for Spinoza, and jus
internum conscientiae or the freedom of the believers’ conscience for Huber.
Accordingly, the history of jus circa sacra is not only the history of the conceptualization
of sovereignty, but also that of freedom of mind. As such, the seventeenth-
century Dutch debates surrounding jus circa sacra form an important
chapter in the history of human rights.
A comparative analysis of the paradigmatic use of Old Testament topics
among contemporary writers in the seventeenth century, such as those
mentioned here, allows for a more nuanced understanding of jus circa sacra
debates and the development of freedom of mind discourse within them.
Many of the biblical quotations and their interpretations found in the treatises,
including the TTP, are less illuminating when considered independently,
but they reveal previously overlooked connections and conversations
when considered in the light of a properly identified ‘web’ of parallel interpretations
of those biblical verses known to each of the authors. Among these
authors, of course, the Jewish philosopher Spinoza stands apart; his way of
connecting himself to this web of interpretation is always highly individualistic,
and is not improperly called a way of ‘playing with’ the premises of his
contemporaries.18 At the same time, however, discussing biblical verses and
their interpretation was an accepted method for discussing contemporary
political and philosophical issues.
This study’s purpose is to explore the TTP as a reaction
to controversies in his milieu regarding the relationship between state,
church, and liberty, with a comparative analysis of biblical quotes as its principal
method. The most immediate historical background of Spinoza’s treatise
still waits to be clarified in many aspects, and this book takes on the task of
clarifying the context of debates about the church-state relationship, and its
intersection with contemporary discussions about the relationship between
philosophy and theology. The recurrent question about revelation’s mediators
is the thread that runs through the succeeding chapters.
Tracing Old Testament topics recurrent in Grotian and Hobbesian discourses on the church-state relationship, Atsuko Fukuoka recontextualizes Spinoza’s Theologico-political Treatise and clarifies its historical import for Dutch debates on religion, state power, and liberty.
Tracing Old Testament topics recurrent in Grotian and Hobbesian discourses on the church-state relationship, Atsuko Fukuoka recontextualizes Spinoza’s Theologico-political Treatise and clarifies its historical import for Dutch debates on religion, state power, and liberty.
Download the book The Sovereign and the Prophets - Spinoza on Grotian and Hobbesian Biblical Argumentation for free or read online
Continue reading on any device:
Last viewed books
Related books
{related-news}
Comments (0)